Observations and Doubts
In many places around the world one can find people with
divergent views. In many of those places, tensions have grown considerably and
taken the form of hateful language and even violence. Tolerance and an openness
to considering alternative views and perspectives seems to be at all-time lows
in some places. Advocacy seems to be displacing evidence. Anger seems to be
displacing thoughtfulness. What can be done?
Earlier in my career, I thought that I could use reason and
logical argumentation to enlighten those suffering from the throes of dogmatism,
prejudice and intolerance. I thought that helping others to develop a
scientific attitude could help cures the ills of a society suffering from
intolerance. Was I wrong to have such thoughts?
What is it to have a
scientific attitude? Some might say that it involves considering beliefs and
statements that could potentially be shown to be false or mistaken as those
beliefs and statements that are worth investigating (for those keeping notes, I
am thinking about Karl Popper’s Conjectures
and Refutations). If the person holding the belief or making the statement
is not willing to consider that it could be wrong, then there seems to be
little to be gained in pursuing discourse with that person based on an
acceptance of the belief or statement if one happens to doubt that belief or
statement. This could be called the walk-away
strategy. The drawback is that no
progress in terms of understanding or openness occurs as a result. I have
walked away too many times.
A somewhat different approach involves thinking about what
underlies thinking and reasoning. It then occurs to me to revisit Ludwig
Wittgenstein’s works. In the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus (you really should be keeping notes), Wittgenstein
observes at remark 2.1 that we picture facts to ourselves. He fails to note
that we also picture things that are not factual to ourselves. Nevertheless,
the remark that we picture facts to ourselves is the kernel notion in a
naturalistic or constructivist epistemology – we create internal
representations to make sense of things that we experience that are new,
unusual or otherwise puzzling. The last remark in the Tractatus is that what we cannot speak about [clearly] we must pass
over in silence. As it happened, there was much that Wittgenstein wanted to
speak about, as is evident in Philosophical
Investigations published after his death. In that posthumous work, he
introduced the notion of language games. Not only do we create internal
representations to make sense of new and puzzling things, we talk about those
representations with others. We engage in language games. Such discourse
represents a re-representation of the internal representations that are
basically hypothetical entities that no one ever directly observes. These two
ideas – creating internal representations and engaging in discourse about those
representations – are the basis of a socio-constructivist epistemology that is
prevalent in some educational and philosophical circles.
Then my mind wanders into ancient gardens and I stumble
across the works of Sextus Empiricus and Outlines
of Pyrrhonism. Since that work was written in Greek, I decided to read it
from back to front. After describing what it is to be a skeptic but before I
read that part, Sextus argues that being a skeptic will result in peace and
tranquility. Is that not odd? Well, in my typical state of anxiety and
confusion, it seems highly desirable. How to achieve such intellectual peace
and tranquility? I had to read the first part to find an answer to that
question.
Basically, becoming a skeptic is recognizing that many
(possibly most) beliefs and statements are open to investigation. A dogmatic
position results when one believes something about which there exists a basis
for doubt or further investigation; a variant of dogmatism occurs when one
believes that there is no possible answer to a question or issue. In both of
those cases, no further inquiry can occur and the discourse is cut off (recall
the walk-away strategy mentioned earlier). A skeptic, however, is someone who
recognizes that further investigation is possible even when the available
evidence apparently favors one or another of the many possible beliefs or positions. A
skeptic, in the world of Sextus Empiricus, is not held captive by his or her beliefs.
I have to admit that from that conclusion (many or most
beliefs are open to further investigation and possible refutation) to
intellectual peace and tranquility is a leap – at least for me (I have short
legs). Nonetheless, I have developed a few suggestions that might lead a student
to a path not yet taken.
The Suggestion
As I am close to retiring after more than 40 years in higher
education, I am beginning to understand the role of a teacher in fostering
inquiry, reasoning and critical thinking. There are two pieces to the puzzle
that I am trying to piece together.
The first is the notion of having questions. The job of a
teacher is to help students have questions – not to help them ask questions or
give them answers. To have a question involves (a) admitting that one does not
know (with certainty or with extremely high confidence) something, (b)
committing time and effort to finding answers, (c) being willing to consider
alternative perspectives and approaches, and (d) being willing to revisit the entire
process again and again (akin to Socrates asking Crito to explain again why he
should escape). It seems to me that all too often, students are taught to have
answers rather than to have questions. Learning how to have questions should be
considered a basic skill, akin to reading Plato’s Symposium, writing love letters, and calculating π (I happen to love transcendental
numbers). If this argument is accepted, then inquiry should be introduced early
and often in primary and secondary education.
The second piece to this puzzle (which seems very difficult
to put together) is a framework that can support a wide variety of inquiries –
that is to say, cases of having questions. One framework that might fit into
this very complicated puzzle (supporting inquiry, reasoning and critical
thinking) involves considering argument forms. An argument can be considered a
collection of statements (premises) offered in support another statement (the
conclusion). A form of scientific reasoning can be mapped onto this notion of
an argument form. Logicians typically distinguish deductive arguments from
non-deductive arguments since the criteria for evaluating them are different.
That distinction is not necessarily relevant to this brief and tenuous
excursion into inquiry learning. The framework I propose also includes assumptions, implications and the links between evidence and conclusion.
The reason for introducing such a framework early in a child’s
education is that it can establish a habit of mind – namely the habit of
thinking of the adequacy of the evidence, the habit of identifying unstated
assumptions that might also merit inquiry, and the habit of looking at the
implications of what one believes. If those habits are established early in a
child’s education, then there is a remote possibility that more children will
begin to think scientifically. Perhaps there is a remote possibility that when
those children become adults that they will be free from dogmas that create
tension, confusion and strife within society. There is a remote possibility.
Concluding Statement
I cannot pretend to have found answers or even useful paths
to follow. I have only been able to create possibilities. With regard to
possibilities, I see several varieties. There are bare possibilities, such as
the possibility that the number of grains of sand on the shores of Iwo Jima at
a particular point in time is an odd number. There are also practical
possibilities, such as the possibility of significantly reducing hunger and
violence in a particular part of the world. Another practical possibility is
that the children of today may indeed become skeptical inquirers (i.e.,
non-dogmatic investigators) and critical thinkers. That last practical
possibility, however, is not likely to occur without the efforts of many of
those involved in such efforts as the Building the Scientific Mind enterprise (see http://www.learndev.org/BtSM2015.html).
No comments:
Post a Comment