Fostering Inquiry, Reasoning and Critical Thinking
J. Michael Spector, PhD, Professor of
Learning Technologies, University
of
North Texas
Observations and Doubts
In many places
around the world one can
find people with divergent
views. In many
of those places, tensions have
grown considerably and taken the form of hateful
language and even
violence. Tolerance and an openness to considering
alternative views and perspectives seems to be at all-time
lows in some places. Advocacy seems to be displacing
evidence. Anger seems to be
displacing thoughtfulness. What can be done?
Earlier in my career, I
thought that I could
use reason and logical argumentation to enlighten those suffering
from the throes of
dogmatism, prejudice and intolerance. I thought that helping
others to develop
a scientific attitude
could help cures the
ills of a society suffering
from intolerance. Was I wrong to have such
thoughts?
What is it
to
have a scientific attitude? Some might say that it involves considering
beliefs and statements
that could potentially be shown to be false
or mistaken as those beliefs and statements are worth
investigating (for those keeping
notes, I am thinking
about Karl Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations). If the
person holding the belief or making
the statement is not willing
to consider that it could
be wrong, then there seems to be
little to be gained in
pursuing discourse with that person based on an acceptance of the belief
or statement
if one happens to doubt that
belief or statement. This could be called the walk-away strategy. The drawback is that no progress
in terms of understanding or openness occurs
as a result. I have walked
away too many times.
A somewhat different
approach involves thinking about what underlies thinking and
reasoning. It then occurs to me
to
revisit Ludwig Wittgenstein’s
works. In the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus (you really should be keeping
notes), Wittgenstein observes at remark
2.1 that we picture facts to ourselves. He fails
to note that we also picture things that are
not factual to ourselves. Nevertheless, the remark
that we picture facts to ourselves is the kernel notion in
a naturalistic or constructivist
epistemology – we create
internal representations to make sense of things that we experience that are new, unusual
or otherwise puzzling.
The last remark in the
Tractatus is that what
we cannot speak about [clearly]
we
must pass over in
silence. As it happened, there was much that Wittgenstein wanted to speak
about, as is evident in Philosophical Investigations published after his death. In that posthumous work, he introduced
the notion of language
games. Not only do we create
internal representations to make sense of
new
and puzzling things, we talk about those
representations with others. We engage in
language games. Such discourse represents a re-representation of the internal
representations that are basically hypothetical entities
that no one ever directly observes. These two ideas
–
creating internal representations and engaging in discourse about those representations – are the basis
of a socio- constructivist epistemology that is prevalent in some educational and
philosophical circles.
Then my mind
wanders into ancient
gardens and I stumble across
the
works of Sextus Empiricus
and Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Since that work was written
in Greek,
I decided to read it
from back to
front. After describing
what it is to be a
skeptic but before I read that part, Sextus
argues that being a
skeptic will result in peace
and tranquility. Is that not odd? Well, in
my typical state of
anxiety and confusion, it seems highly
desirable. How to achieve
such intellectual peace and
tranquility? I had to read the first part
to find an answer to that question.
Basically, becoming a skeptic involves recognizing that many (possibly
most) beliefs and statements are open to investigation. A dogmatic position results when one believes
something about which there exists a basis for
doubt or further investigation; a variant
of dogmatism occurs when one believes that there
is no possible
answer to a question or issue. In
both of those cases, no further
inquiry can occur and the
discourse is cut
off (recall the
walk-away strategy mentioned earlier).
A skeptic, however, is someone who recognizes
that further investigation is possible
even when the available
evidence apparently favors one or another of the many possible
beliefs or positions. A skeptic, in the world of Sextus
Empiricus, is not held captive by his or
her beliefs.
I have to admit that from
that conclusion (many or
most beliefs are open to further
investigation and possible
refutation) to intellectual peace and tranquility is a leap – at
least for me (I
have short legs). Nonetheless, I have developed a few suggestions that might lead a student
to a path not yet taken.
The Suggestion
As I am close to retiring after more than 40 years
in higher education, I am beginning to understand the role of a teacher in fostering inquiry, reasoning and critical thinking. There are two pieces
to the puzzle that I am trying to
piece together.
The first is the
notion of having questions.
The
job of a teacher
is to help students have questions – not to help them ask questions or give them answers.
To have a question involves (a) admitting that one does
not
know (with certainty or with extremely high confidence) something, (b) committing
time and effort
to finding answers, (c) being willing to consider alternative
perspectives and approaches, and (d) being willing to revisit the entire process
again and again (akin
to Socrates asking Crito to explain again why he should escape). It seems
to me that all too
often students are taught to
have answers rather
than to have questions. Learning
how to have questions should be considered a basic skill, akin to
reading
Plato’s Symposium, writing
love letters, and calculating
Ï€
(I happen
to love transcendental numbers). If this
argument is accepted, then inquiry should
be introduced early and often in primary and secondary education.
The second
piece to this puzzle (which seems very
difficult to put together)
is a framework that can support
a wide variety of inquiries
– that is to
say, cases of having questions.
One framework
that might fit
into this very complicated puzzle (supporting inquiry, reasoning and critical thinking) involves considering argument forms. An
argument can
be considered a collection of statements
(premises) offered in support of another statement (the conclusion). A form of scientific reasoning
can be mapped onto
this notion of an argument form. Logicians typically
distinguish deductive arguments from non- deductive arguments
since the criteria for evaluating them are
different. That distinction is not necessarily
relevant to this brief and tenuous excursion into inquiry learning.
The
figure below depicts
the general form of
an argument. The reason for introducing
such a framework
early in a child’s education
is that it can establish
a habit of mind – namely the habit of thinking of the adequacy
of the evidence,
the habit of identifying unstated assumptions that might also
merit inquiry, and the habit of looking at the
implications of what one believes.
If those habits are established early
in a child’s education, then there is
a remote possibility that more children
will begin to think scientifically. Perhaps
there is a remote possibility that when those children become adults
that they will be free
from dogmas that create tension,
confusion and strife within society. There is a remote
possibility.
Concluding Statement
I cannot pretend to
have found answers or even
useful paths to follow. I have only been able
to create possibilities. With
regard to possibilities, I see several
varieties. There are bare possibilities,
such as the possibility that the number of grains of
sand on the shores
of Iwo Jima at
a particular
point in time is an
odd number. There are
also practical possibilities, such as the possibility of significantly reducing
hunger and violence in a particular part of the world.
Another practical possibility is that the children of today may indeed become skeptical inquirers (i.e., non-dogmatic investigators)
and critical thinkers. That last practical
possibility, however, is not likely to occur without
the efforts of many of those involved
in such efforts as the
Building the Scientific Mind
enterprise.
No comments:
Post a Comment